The Theory of Cultural Racism | |||
[Moderator's Note: Professor James
M. Blount is recentlydeceased. This article is being posted posthumously to
honor his legacy. A big thank you
goes out to Henry C K
Liu <hliu@mindspring.com>
for making this available.]
http://www.blackwellpublishers.co.uk/journals/anti/
Antipode: A Radical Journal of
Geography
Volume 23 (1992) [Pages 289-299]
The Theory of Cultural Racism
By James M. Blaut
<jblaut@uic.edu>, Department of Geography,
University of Illinois at Chicago
i. Theory and Practice
Very few academics these days
consider themselves to be
racists, and calling someone a
racist is deeply offensive.
Yet racism in the universities is
just as pervasive, just as
dangerous, as it was a generation
ago. Nowadays we seem to
have a lot of racism but very few
racists. How do you
explain this paradox?
The place to begin is to notice
the essential difference
between racist theory and racist
practice. Racism most
fundamentally is practice: the
practice of discrimination,
at all levels, from personal
abuse to colonial oppression.
Racism is a form of practice
which has been tremendously
important in European society for
several hundred years,
important in the sense that it is
an essential part of the
way the European capitalist
system maintains itself.
Racist practice, like all
practice, is cognized,
rationalized, justified, by a
theory, a belief-system about
the nature of reality and the
behavior which is appropriate
to this cognized reality. (The
word "theory" is better in
this context than the word
"ideology," because we are
talking about a system of
empirical beliefs, not about the
cultural bindings of belief.) But
theory and practice do not
have a one- to-one relationship.
One form of practice can be
underlain by various different
theories. Since
racism-as-practice, that is,
discrimination, is an essential
part of the system, we should not
be surprised to discover
that it has been supported by a
historical sequence of
different theories, each
consistent with the intellectual
environment of a given era. Nor
should we be surprised to
find that the sequent theories
are so different from one
another that the racist theory of
one epoch is in part a
refutation of the racist theory
of the preceding epoch.
Putting the matter in a somewhat
over-simplified form, the
dominant racist theory of the
early nineteenth century was a
biblical argument, grounded in
religion; the dominant racist
theory of the period from about
1850 to 1950 was a
biological argument, grounded in
natural science; the racist
theory of today is mainly a
historical argument, grounded in
the idea of culture history or
simply culture. Today's
racism is cultural racism.
I will try to show, in this
paper, what cultural racism is
all about and how and why it has
largely supplanted
biological racism (at least among
academics). To start
things off, I'll explain the
paradox that, today, in
universities, we have racism but
few racists.
Generally, when we call a person
a racist in the academic
world of today we are accusing
this person of believing in
the hereditary, biological
superiority of people of one
so-called race over people of
another so-called race, with
the implication that
discrimination is justified, explained,
rationalized, by the underlying
biological theory. But
hardly anybody believes in this
theory anymore. Most
academics believe that the
typical members of what used to
be called inferior races have a
capacity equal to that of
other so-called races, but they
have not been able to
realize this capacity. They have
not learned the things one
needs to know to be treated as an
equal. They have not
learned how to think rationally,
as mental adults. They have
not learned how to behave in
appropriate ways, as social
adults. The problem is culture,
not biology. And, naturally,
the inequality will disappear in
the course of time. But in
the meantime, discrimination is
perfectly justified. Of
course it is not called
"discrimination" in this newer
theory. It is a matter of
treating each person in a way that
is appropriate to his or her
abilities. The people of one
race -- pardon me: one ethnic
group -- demonstrate greater
abilities than those of other
ethnic groups, abilities in
IQ, ACT, and SAT test-taking, in
"need achievement
motivation," in avoidance of
criminality, and so on. Given
that they have these higher
realized abilities, they should
be given greater rewards. They
should be admitted to
college, be granted Ph.D.s and
tenure, and the rest. And so
racist practice persists under
the guidance of a theory
which actually denies the
relevance of race. The differences
between humans which justify
discriminatory treatment are
differences in acquired
characteristics: in culture.
Another way of putting this is to
say that cultural racism
substitutes the cultural category
"European" for the racial
category "white." We no
longer have a superior race; we
have, instead, a superior
culture. It is "European culture,"
or "Western culture,"
"the West" (see Amin 1989). What
counts is culture, not color.
ii. Religious Racism
The notion of European cultural
superiority is not a new
one. Early in the 19th century,
Europeans considered
themselves to be superior because
they are Christians and a
Christian god must naturally
favor His own followers,
particularly those who worship
Him according to the proper
sacrament. He will take care of
such matters as hereditary
abilities, thus making it easier
for His followers to
thrive, multiply, progress,
conquer the world. He will even
make certain that the physical
environment in which
Christians live is more favorable
than the environment
surrounding heathens: hence
Europe's climate is neither too
hot nor too cold, not
"torrid" nor "frigid" but nicely
"temperate." In a word:
it was believed that the people of
Europe, traditional Christendom,
possess cultural
superiority, biological
superiority, even environmental
superiority, but all of this
flows from a supernatural
cause. This was the theory which,
in the period up to
roughly the middle of the 19th
century, underlay most racist
practice.
Note that the religious theory of
racism was an empirical
argument. The cause was
supernatural, but the effects were
straightforward facts. God had
created white people, in a
region which Europeans considered
to be their own cultural
hearth: the "Bible
Lands." The Garden of Eden was thought by
many scholars to have been
located somewhere around the
headwaters of the Tigris river,
in the healthful, temperate,
mountains of Armenia, not far
from Mt. Ararat, where Noah
landed, not far from the Caucasus
Mountains which were known
to be the home of the Caucasian
race, and (as was often
pointed out) in the same
temperate latitude as Greece and
Rome (see, e.g., Lord 1869).
There was no such thing as
early cultural evolution, since
Man was given agriculture,
cities, and civilization in the
days of Genesis. All of
pre-Christian history took place
among white people in a
small piece of the earth's
surface, roughly between Rome and
Mesopotamia. The rest of the
world was uninhabited. People
migrated from this hearth to, and
so populated, Asia and
Africa. During the course of this
exodus they became
non-white, and they degenerated
(Bowler 1989), and lost the
arts of civilization (although
Asians retained some of these
arts).1 All of this was
considered to be historical fact. It
followed, then, that the white
race has always been superior
and still remains superior, and
for very evident reasons. In
short: an empirical theory,
giving scientific justification
for racist practice.
iii. Biological Racism
Toward the end of the 19th
century, naturalistic arguments
had displaced biblical and
theological arguments in most
scholarly discourse. But it
should not be thought that
religious racism (as theory) had
entirely disappeared. In
many contexts thereafter, this
theory was (and still is)
used to justify racist practice
in which people of one
religion oppress people of another
on grounds of this, or
some very similar, theory. An
obvious contemporary example
is Israeli expansionism. God gave
all of Palestine (and
more) to the Jews long ago, so
the Jews have overriding
rights to all of the God-given
land, and can expel anyone
else from that land on the basis
of this absolute principle.
It is quibbling to object that
this is not racism because
Jews are not a race. It is
religious racism.
The secularization of thought
after about 1850 made it
necessary to rest racist practice
in a new and different
theory. Religious racism had
already established the
causality by which God gives
better heredity to Christians,
and this argument could now be
adapted to assert the genetic
superiority of the so-called
white race, grounding this
argument now in the immensely
influential biological
theories of the period, notably
Darwinism and (later)
Mendelianism. The genetic
superiority of the so-called white
race was now believed in
axiomatically by nearly all social
theorists. The cultural superiority
of Europeans (a category
vaguely identified with the white
race) was also believed
in, also axiomatically. Cultural
superiority was mainly,
though not entirely, considered
to be an effect of racial
superiority. (I say not entirely
because various other sorts
of naturalistic causality were
also invoked: Europe's
environment is superior. Or
Europe's cultural priority
originated in the mysterious and
impenetrable mists of
prehistory. Or no causation was
postulated because none was
thought to be needed. For some
thinkers, among them Max
Weber, all of these arguments
were heaped together in a
melange of race, culture, and
geography.) But it is fair to
say that the hereditary
superiority of the white race was
considered to be the single most
important explanati
multipart fon for the white man's
obvious superiority in
culture. This was the era of
classical or biological racism.
After the First World War, the
theory of white biological
superiority began to lose force
in the scholarly communities
of most (not all) European
countries. This reflected several
causes. Some were internal to
intellectual progress, in, for
instance, culture theory (e.g.,
Boas, Radin), psychological
theory (e.g., Lewin),
philosophies grounded in experience
rather than the Cartesian-Kantian
a priori (e.g., Dewey,
Whitehead, Mead). One external
causes was the rise of
egalitarian values, notably
socialism, which militatated
against theories of innate
superiority and inferiority. A
second external cause, a very
powerful one, was opposition
to Nazism, which almost
necessarily meant opposition to
doctrines of biological
superiority and inferiority.
iv. Cultural Racism
All of this notwithstanding,
biological racism remained
somewhat respectable until the
1950s and 1960s, the
classical era of national
liberation and civil rights
struggles. Racist practice now
needed a new theory. At this
time, mainstream scholarship was
being assigned -- quite
literally: with funds and jobs provided
-- the task of
formulating a theoretical
structure which would rationalize
continued dominance of
communities of color in the Third
World and at home. Such a theory
would have to accept two
anti-biological-racist
propositions which were axiomatic in
Non-European communities: that
Europeans are not innately
superior, and that economic
development can bring
non-Europeans to the same level
as Europeans. The problem
was to show that non-Europeans,
though equal to Europeans in
innate capacity, cannot develop
economically to the European
level unless these societies
voluntarily accept the
continued domination by European
countries and corporations,
that is, neocolonialism.
The outcome of this truly massive
theory- building effort
was the theory of "modernization."
This theory argued, in
essence, that non-Europeans are
not racially, but rather
culturally backward in comparison
to Europeans because of
their history: their lesser
cultural evolution. And it is
for this reason that they are
poor. So they must follow,
under European guidance and
"tutelage," the path already
trodden by Europeans as the only
means of overcoming
backwardness. Non-Europeans were
thereby defined as inferior
in attained level of achievement,
not potential for
achievement. This was the real
essence of cultural racism.
One of the most interesting and
important aspects of this
theory-building campaign was the
deification of Max Weber by
various groups of social
scientists, among them the
Parsonian structural-
functionalists (see Peet 1991) and
"traditional mind"
theorists like McClelland, most of whom
were involved directly or
indirectly in the
modernization-theory construction
project. Weber himself, a
half-century before, had
expressed the then-dominant
European views concerning
non-Europeans, with some small
improvements. Weber's argument,
though partially grounded in
biological racism (see, e.g.,
Weber 1958: 30; 1967: 387;
1981: 299, 379; 1951: 231-232),
could easily be detached
from that grounding because most
of what he wrote about
European superiority was
axiomatic argumentation about the
uniqueness of the European mind
-- its rationality, its
spiritual capacity -- and
historical argumentation about the
unique rise within Europe, and Europe
alone, of institutions
and structures which were the
source of modernity. (See in
particular Weber 1951; 1958;
1981.) Neither rationality nor
structure was (in general)
connected backward to race, as
effect of a prime cause. Thus the
Weberian argument could
be, and was, detached from race
and presented as a theory of
modernization grounded in the
uniqueness of European
mentality and culture, permanent
qualities which throughout
history gave Europeans a
continuously more rapid course
toward modernity than
non-Europeans.2 Those who think that
Weber became popular in the 1950s
and 1960s because of his
well-known opposition to the
Marxist theory of the rise of
capitalism are missing the bigger
picture. Weber, and
Weberianism, became important at
that time mainly because
Weber provided contemporary
social scientists with a theory
of modernization, essentially an
elegant and scholarly
restatement of colonial-era ideas
about the uniqueness of
European rationality and the
uniqueness of European culture
history. Weber was to
neocolonialism what Marx was to
socialism. In a manner of
speaking, Weber was the godfather
of cultural racism.
Cultural racism, as a theory,
needs to prove the superiority
of Europeans, and needs to do so
without recourse to the
older arguments from religion and
from biology. How does it
do this? By recourse to history
-- by constructing a
characteristic theory of cultural
(and intellectual)
history. The claim is simply made
that nearly all of the
important cultural innovations
which historically generate
cultural progress occurred first
in Europe, then, later,
diffused to the non-European
peoples (Blaut forthcoming
1992). Therefore, at each moment
in history Europeans are
more advanced than non- Europeans
in overall cultural
development (though not
necessarily in each particular
culture trait), and they are more
progressive than
non-Europeans. This is asserted
as a great bundle of
apparently empirical facts about
invention and innovation,
not only of material and
technological traits but of
political and social traits like
the state, the market, the
family. The tellers of this tale
saturate history with
European inventions, European
progressiveness, European
progress.
This massive bundle of
purportedly empirical, factual
statements was woven together by
means of a modern form of
the 19th-century theory of
Eurocentric diffusionism (Blaut
1987a; 1987b). This theory
evolved as a justification and
rationalization for classical colonialism.
It asserted, in
essence, the following
propositions about the world as a
whole and throughout all of
history. (1) The world has a
permanent center, or core, and a
permanent periphery. The
center is Greater Europe, that
is, the continent of Europe
plus, for ancient times, the
Bible Lands and, for modern
times, the countries of European
settlement overseas. The
core sector, Greater Europe, is
naturally inventive,
innovative, progressive. (2) The
periphery, the non-European
world, naturally remains
traditional, culturally sluggish or
stagnant. (3) The basic reason
why Europe is progressive,
innovative, etc., is some quality
of mind or spirit, some
"rationality," peculiar
to Europeans. (4) Progress occurs in
the periphery as a result of the
diffusion, the outward
spread, of new and innovative
traits from the core to the
periphery. The diffusion process
itself is natural. It
consists of the spread of
European ideas, European
colonialism, European settlers,
and European commodities.
Notice that the basic theory can
be driven by religious,
biological, or cultural motors.
In the modern, post-1945
form of the theory, the motor was
culture, or rather culture
history. The theory itself was
softened in some ways, for
instance conceding that some
progress takes place in
non-Europe (in spite of cultural
"blockages"), but the
structure remained basically the
same.
Modern diffusionism therefore
depicts a world in which
Europeans have always been the
most progressive people, and
non-Europeans are backward, and
permanently the recipients
of progressive ideas, things, and
people from Europe. It
follows that progress for the
periphery, today as always in
the past, must consist of the
continued diffusion of
European "rationality"
and institutions, European culture
and control. The periphery,
today, includes the Third World,
along with Third World minorities
embedded in the
European-dominated countries like
the United States, in
ghettos, reservations, prisons,
migrant-labor camps.
The main proposition here is a
kind of Eurocentric
historical tunnel-vision which
can be called "tunnel
history." Historical
causation occurs, basically, in Europe
and its self-proclaimed culture
hearth, the ancient Near
East. (Examples: the origin of
agriculture, cities, states,
science, democracy, feudalism,
private property, discovery,
capitalism, industry...)
Non-Europe participates in history
mainly as recipient of diffusions
from Europe. The most
important part of tunnel history
concerns the world before
1492. (And 1992 is a peculiarly
appropriate year in which to
point this out.) The essential
argument is this: Europe was
advancing more rapidly than the
other civilizations of the
world, and was more advanced than
these other civilizations,
at the very beginning of the
modern era, prior to the rise
of capitalism and modernization,
and prior to the beginnings
of colonialism. Therefore, the
superiority of Europeans as
individuals and of European
culture has very, very old roots
and, by inference, is natural and
fundamental. This
proposition accomplishes
everything that biological racism
accomplished and more; indeed,
there is a structural as well
as functional parallelism between
this doctrine and
biological racism. It argues, in
essence, that a cultural,
not genetic, superiority appeared
in the European cultural
pool very long ago and, just like
genetic superiority, it
has led ever since to a greater
rate of development for
Europe and to a level of
development which, at each moment
in history, is higher than that
of non-European cultures.
Something occurred long ago in
European culture which pushed
it into rapid progress. This
something then continued to
operate to generate progress
throughout all of later
history. In effect: a cultural
gene, or cultural mutation.
But cultural racism claims that a
vast number of these
European cultural causes of
progress, cultural mutations,
occurred, throughout history, one
after another, each adding
further impetus to the progress
of Europe, each pushing
Europe farther ahead of all other
civilizations.
v. A Few Examples
Before I give a few illustrative
examples of modern
cultural-racist theories, I have
to offer two introductory
comments to avoid
misunderstanding -- serious
misunderstanding. First:
Precisely for the reason that we
have, these days, so much racism
yet so few racists,
cultural racism is not, in most
cases, propagated by people
whom we would want to label
"racists." The doctrine is
theory, not prejudice. Those
scholars who advocate one or
another form of it are people who
believe that they are
dealing with facts, and with the
policy implications of
these facts. Most of them reject
prejudice and are not
prejudiced. They simply believe that
there are
straightforward empirical
reasons, grounded in cultural
differences, which explain why
some groups and individuals
are backward.
Secondly, it is very important to
distinguish between those
statements which merely assert
that some culture traits
survive for long periods of time
and those statements which
assert that some ancient, or at
any rate tenacious, culture
traits explain the superiority of
this culture and the
inferiority of that one. Change
is the normal condition in
human cultures. If there is lack
of change, it is either
because the members of a culture
do not want to discard some
cherished traits or have no
choice because of impinging
circumstances. No human group is
so stupid as to cherish
misery, want, and death. Culture
traits which generate or
worsen such things are discarded,
and quite deliberately so.
(There are exceptions to this
generalization, but they are
very rare, though much
publicized, particularly in freshman
textbooks.) Cultural ecologists
speak of a "culture core"
consisting of those traits and
institutions which lie close
to the realm of human survival:
matters of life and death
(see in particular Steward 1955).
This part of culture is
very plastic, very adaptive. People
resist change in other
parts of their culture (such as
religion). But it is very
questionable to infer that human
groups will retain any
traits if doing so is destructive
to their livelihood and
survival. Therefore, whenever you
hear a statement like
"this group is unprogressive
because of its religious
values," or "that group
is poor because its members are
tradition-minded and opposed to
innovation," you should be
on the lookout for cultural
racism. It is one thing to
respect culture, and to appreciate
cultural differences, and
quite another thing to rank human
groups on cultural
criteria, and to claim then that
you have explained history.
Now some examples.
1. Many historians, today as in
the past, claim to find a
uniqueness in the culture of very
early Europe, something
which they connect with the early
Indo-Europeans (e.g.,
Lelekov 1985; Baechler 1988) or
the Germans (e.g.,
Macfarlane 1978; 1986; Crone
1989) or the Iron-Age peasants
(Mann 1986; 1988), and quite regularly
attach to the ancient
Greeks as contradistinct from
their non-Indo-European
neighbors (see the analysis of
this matter in Bernal 1987).
In Marx's Germany, the
conventional wisdom was that ancient
Germans were uniquely
freedom-loving, innovative,
individualistic, aggressive, and
rational; the modern form
of the doctrine does not depart
much from this formulation
except as it admits Celts and
Greeks to membership; no
modern evidence adds support.
Here, now, are some of the
historical theories built upon
the doctrine. (i) Ancient
Europeans were uniquely inventive
and technologically
innovative, and thereafter
remained so (Jones 1981). (ii)
Ancient Europeans acquired a
unique love of freedom, which
matured then into a democratic
state (Mann 1986; Hall,
1985). (iii) Ancient Europeans,
because of or in close
association with their
individualism, adopted a unique
family type which then acted to
favor progressiveness,
innovativeness, and, incipiently,
capitalism (Jones 1981;
Macfarlane 1986; Todd 1985).
2. Many theories begin Europe's
uniqueness with Roman times,
or slightly earlier, often
focusing on the Church, or the
partly pre-Christian "Judeo-
Christian tradition," or the
later Western Church. Different
theories find different
causes for the emergence of the
new, and unique, and
uniquely progressive culture. The
effects also are manifold.
For instance: (i) Lynn White,
Jr,. argues that the
Judeo-Christian teleology
explains Western technological
inventiveness and innovativeness
(see Blaut forthcoming
1992); (ii) Anderson (1974) sees
something uniquely
scientific and intellectual in
the cultural heirs to the
Greeks and Romans; (iii) Werner
(1988) believes that
European s became uniquely
progressive because Christianity
alone gave prominence to the
individual.
3. A great many present-day
historians believe that
Europeans long ago acquired an
ability to resist the
Malthusian disasters which
supposedly blocked development in
every other culture, some of the
arguments starting with the
ancient Iron Age folk, some with
an amalgam of Germanic and
Christian elements, some with
medieval Northwest-Europeans
(see Mann 1986; Macfarlane 1986;
Jones 1981; Stone 1977;
Crone 1989 and many others). This
then becomes a general
theory explaining what some call
the "European miracle," by
arguing that the (mythically
unique) European family,
nuclear, late-marrying,
companionate, led to population
control (Hall [1985: 131] speaks
of "the relative continence
of the European family");
led also to a capitalist mentality
(Macfarlane 1986; Laslett 1988);
even led unmarried European
men to go forth and conquer the
world because of their
sexual frustration (Stone 1977:
54).
4. Paralleling all of these
arguments is a set of arguments
to the effect that non-Europeans,
long ago, acquired
cultural qualities which blocked
development, or -- this is
perhaps the more common
formulation -- such qualities are
"traditional," and
therefore have always been present in
non-European cultures. Todd
(1985: 192) thinks that Africans
and African-Americans do not
progress because the African
family has always lacked the
father-figure. Many other
scholars point either to specific
old traits in specific
cultures as causes of non-change,
or else depict a
world-wide zone of
"traditional cultures" -- including
almost all non-European cultures
-- which "traditionally"
lacked rationality, or
achievement motivation, or sexual
continence, or some other quality
necessary to forward
historical motion. It must be
added that this argument is
also used very routinely to
explain the poverty of minority
people in countries like the
United States. When, for
instance, lack of progress among
Mexicans and Puerto Ricans
in this country is attributed to
the "traditional culture,"
its supposed "fatalistic
attitudes," "docility," etc., etc.,
this is still cultural racism
even though the source of the
cultural argument is not ancient
but rather a kind of
undated "traditional
society."
Cultural racism is rooted most
fundamentally in historical
mythology about the priority of
Europe and thus the
supposedly more mature, evolved,
rational character of
Europeans, today, at home and
abroad. By way of closing this
short paper I will simply note
that, even if all of the
roots are torn out, the vine will
not wither: it will grow
other roots, a new theory of
racism, unless racism is
attacked, not as theory but as
practice.
NOTES
1 A minority of scholars accepted
the theory of polygenesis,
according to which non-white
people are not descendants of
Adam and Eve, and did not migrate
to Africa and Asia but
were placed there by God along
with the beasts. See Bowler
(1989).
2 Weber also, here and there,
invoked the natural
environment. He argued, for
instance, the already
traditional contrast, aridity-irrigation-Oriental-
despotism
versus "rainfed
farming"-European- democracy-rationality:
see Weber 1976: 84, 131, 157;
1951: 16, 21, 25; 1981: 56-57.
REFERENCES
Amin, Samir (1989) Eurocentrism.
New York: Monthly Review
Press.
Anderson, P. (1974) Passages from
antiquity to feudalism.
London: NLB.
Baechler, J. (1988) The origins
of modernity. In: Baechler
et al. (Eds.) Europe and the rise
of capitalism, pp. 39-65.
Baechler, J., M. Mann, and J.
Hall (Eds.) (1988) Europe and
the rise of capitalism. Oxford:
Basil Blackwell.
Bernal, M. (1987) Black Athena,
vol. 1. London: Free
Association Books.
Blaut, J. (1987a) Diffusionism: A
uniformitarian critique.
Annals of the Association of
American Geographers 77:30-47.
Blaut, J. (1987b) The national
question. London: Zed Books.
Blaut, J. (Forthcoming 1992)
Fourteen ninety-two. Political
Geography Quarterly, vol. 11, no.
3.
Bowler, P. J. (1989) The
invention of progress: The
Victorians and the past. Oxford:
Basil Blackwell.
Crone, P. (1989) Pre-industrial
societies. Oxford: Basil
Blackwell.
Lord, J. (1869) Ancient states
and empires: For colleges and
schools. New York: Charles
Scribner.
Hall, J. (1985) Powers and
liberties: The causes and
consequences of the rise of the
West. Oxford: Basil
Blackwell.
Jones, E. L. (1981) The European
miracle. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Laslett, P. (1988) The European
family and early
industrialization. In: Baechler,
et al. (Eds.) Europe and
the rise of capitalism, pp.
234-242.
Lelekov, L. (1985) Discussion.
Round-table: State and law in
the ancient Orient. Social
Sciences (USSR Academy of
Sciences), no. 3, 1985, pp.
189-191.
Macfarlane, A. (1978) The origins
of English individualism.
Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Macfarlane, A. (1986) Marriage
and love in England:
1300-1840. Oxford: Basil
Blackwell.
Mann, M. (1986) The sources of
social power, vol. 1: The
history of power from the
beginning to A.D. 1760. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Mann, M. (1988) European
development: Approaching a
historical explanation. In:
Baechler, et al. (Eds.) Europe
and the rise of capitalism, pp.
6-19.
Peet, J. R. (1991) Global
capitalism: Theories of societal
development. London: Routledge.
Steward, J. (1955) Theory of
culture change. Urbana:
University of Illinois Press.
Stone, L. (1977) The family, sex
and marriage in England
1500- 1800. New York: Harper and
Row.
Todd, E. (1985) The explanation
of ideology. Oxford: Basil
Blackwell.
Weber, M. (1951) The religion of
China. New York: Free
Press.
Weber, M. (1958) The Protestant
ethic and the spirit of
capitalism. New York: Scribner's.
Weber;. M. (1976) The agrarian
sociology of ancient
civilizations. London: NLB.
Weber, Max (1981) General
economic history. New Brunswick:
Transaction Books.
Werner, K. (1988) Political and
social structures of the
West. In: Baechler, et al. (Eds.)
Europe and the rise of
capitalism, pp. 169-184.
Copyright (c) 1992-2001 James M.
Blaut. All Rights Reserved.